The Argumentative Jew

To the women and men of Kesher Israel

The most common understanding of disagreement, in the private sphere and the public one, is that it represents a failure. A single understanding, a shared understanding, is preferred to a multiplicity of understandings, which is rejected as an epistemologically fallen condition. We begin with many, but we aspire to one: The grip of the holistic fantasy is profound. Disagreement is a kind of fragmentation, but we wish to be made whole. The many factors that are responsible for intellectual disharmony—rhetorical, conceptual, psychological, cultural, political—are regarded pejoratively as impediments that need to be refuted or discarded, as obstacles in the way of a higher arrangement. That higher arrangement is consensus. Who does not prefer consensus to conflict? Is quarrelsomeness not a vice? Surely a quarrel is a kind of conflict, a state of affairs in need of correction. A quarrel demands resolution and reconciliation. To see things differently is to surrender to difference, whereas sameness or similarity of perspective brings us closer and even unites us. The dream of intellectual concord is also a dream of social concord. The abolition of disagreement, when it is not coerced, is a promise of union and peace.

Recently I came upon a fine example of this consensualist mentality. In 1943, not long before she starved herself to death in England in solidarity with the people of occupied France, Simone Weil wrote a short essay called “On the Abolition of All Political Parties.” It was published posthumously in 1950, and it has recently appeared in an English translation by my late friend Simon Leys. Weil begins her essay with an endorsement of Rousseau and proceeds to develop her own alarmingly Rousseauist vision of perfect society-wide agreement. “Rousseau took as his starting point two premises,” she writes. “First, reason perceives and chooses what is just and innocently useful, whereas every crime is motivated by passion. Second, reason is identical in all men, whereas their passions most often differ. From this it follows that if, on a common issue, everyone thinks alone and then expresses his opinion, and if afterwards all these opinions are collected and compared, most probably they will coincide inasmuch as they are just and reasonable, whereas they will differ inasmuch as they are unjust or mistaken. It is only this type of reasoning that allows one to conclude that a universal consensus may point at the truth. Truth is one.” Weil describes these assumptions as the basis of “our republican ideal.” There exists, of course, another republican ideal, which recognizes the inevitability, and even the nobility, of “faction” and chooses compromise and respect over conformity and massified certitude. Reading Weil, one yearns for Madison. Weil’s remarks also nicely illustrate the way in which a horror of disagreement may culminate in a philosophical monism. It is hard to stay away from metaphysics when one’s subject is truth.

Simone Weil in the School of Yavne

But there exists another school of thought about these questions. It may be found in ancient and early modern India, as Amartya Sen showed in his great essay “The Argumentative Indian,” but its most sophisticated and most robust home is in Judaism, from its beginnings in ancient rabbinical literature all the way to the present day. The Jewish tradition—the tradition of the argumentative Jew—is a long and great challenge to the consensualist mentality. It repudiates, sometimes in theory, always in practice, the cult of unanimity. It displays an almost erotic relationship to controversy. (Like all erotic relationships, this one sometimes devolves into decadence, which in the early modern centuries was known as pilpul.) In the Jewish tradition, disagreement is not only real, it is also ideal—at least in the unredeemed world, which is the only world we know. In its millennia of disputations, even mistaken opinions are not without legitimacy. Minority opinions are not obsolete opinions: They are preserved alongside majority opinions because their reasoning may one day be useful again. Arguments that are adjudicated practically remain alive theoretically. Indeed, both sides of a particular argument may be “the words of the living God.”

The full text of the talmudic passage is this: “Rabbi Aba said in the name of Samuel: For three years the house of Shammai and the house of Hillel disagreed. The former declared: the law should be made according to us, and the latter declared, the law should be made according to us. Then a heavenly voice proclaimed: These opinions and those opinions are the words of the living God, and the law is according to the house of Hillel.” The passage seems to shut down the very debates that it has just sacralized—except that the establishment of the law does not dissolve the legal discussion. The argument survives the decision, which is made among the elders according to majority rule, so that the community may function. But the argument was never itself purely functional. It was, instead, intrinsically valuable. (A practical spirit motivated also the medieval and early modern enterprise of legal codification, but insofar as the codes represented a suspension of the work of analysis, a claim to intellectual closure, they were ferociously opposed.)

This same epic quarrel between the house of Hillel and the house of Shammai is described in a mishnah as “a quarrel for the sake of heaven [which therefore] will endure.” The endurance of a quarrel: What sort of aspiration is this? It is the aspiration of a mentality that is genuinely rigorous and genuinely pluralistic. The tradition of commentary on that mishnah is a kind of history of Jewish views on intellectual inquiry—from the Levant in the 15th century, for example, there is Ovadiah Bertinoro’s remark that “only by means of debate will truth be established,” an uncanny anticipation of Milton and Mill, and from Hungary in the 19th century there is the gloss by Rabbi Moses Schick, who himself had a role in a community-wide schism, that “sometimes it is our duty to make a quarrel . . . For the sake of truth we are not only permitted to make a quarrel, we are obligated to make a quarrel.”

And argument is emphatically man-made. In the talmudic passage cited here, we witness a moment of high religious drama: the abdication of the divine from the human quest for truth. The heavenly voice announces the permanent validity of both sides of an argument and leaves the labor of clarification in our hands. The sacralization of disagreement in Judaism is accompanied by the renunciation of any heavenly role in the attempt to verify legal and philosophical propositions. There is even a midrash that imagines God himself sowing the Torah with perplexities, by imbuing each of his edicts with “49 reasons to rule ‘pure’ and 49 reasons to rule ‘impure.” We are not given the answers. We must find them. At least intellectually, this God has absconded.

“It is not in the heavens”: The scriptural phrase became a recurring refrain. Disputation is an entirely immanent activity. This is an extraordinary expression of confidence in reason and in the mortals who engage in reason. In this practice of earthly self-
reliance, thought is preferred to epiphany, and revelation is a thing of the past. (There are a few works of medieval Jewish jurisprudence that claim to derive their rulings in one way or another “from the heavens,” but a close inspection of their conclusions shows that their claim to a transcendent origin of human opinion is a theological and literary conceit.) Since the end of prophecy and divination, ideas and practices must be validated by principles and by reasoning from principles. Certain problems, to be sure, will not find their solutions, as the ancient rabbis said, until the arrival of Elijah, that is, until the advent of the messiah; but that is really a mythological way of saying that those problems are, to borrow the old phrase of a British philosopher, essentially contested. We are to learn to live with disagreement and not to think less of it because it cannot be miraculously consummated.

 

Learning to live with disagreement, moreover, is a way of learning to live with each other. Etymologically, the term machloket refers to separation and division, but the culture of machloket is not in itself separatist and divisive. This is in part because all the parties to any particular disagreement share certain metaphysical and historical assumptions about the foundations of their identity. But beyond those general axioms, the really remarkable feature of the Jewish tradition of machloket is that it is itself a basis for community. The community of contention, the contentious community, is not as paradoxical as it may seem. The parties to a disagreement are members of the disagreement; they belong to the group that wrestles together with the same perplexity, and they wrestle together for the sake of the larger community to which they all belong, the community that needs to know how Jews should behave and live. A quarrel is evidence of coexistence. The rabbinical tradition is full of rival authorities and rival schools—it owes a lot of its excitement to those grand and even bitter altercations—but the rivalries play themselves out within the unified framework of the shared search. There is dissent without dissension, and yet things change. Intellectual discord, if it is practiced with methodological integrity, is compatible with social peace.

The absence of the God’s-eye view of an issue, and the consequent recognition of the limitations of all individual perspectives, has a humbling effect. A universe of controversy is a universe of tolerance. Machloket is not schism, and the difference is crucial. Though disagreement may lead to sectarianism, most disagreement in the history of this ever-thinking people has been contained, and has been brilliantly developed, on this side of sectarianism. I do not mean to exaggerate the loveliness of the system: There has been heresy and there has been heterodoxy, and Jews have persecuted other Jews for their opinions. Intellectual integrity is always a risk to community, because some minds may think themselves, rightly or wrongly, beyond the limits. But the tradition of Jewish debate, especially legal debate, is striking for how rich it remains within the limits. Whether or not heresy and heterodoxy are forms of heroism, it is important to acknowledge that fidelity, and the internal growth of a tradition inside its carefully examined boundaries, may also be heroic.

Thus described, the Jewish model of quarrelsome unity may be hard to grasp. Can a religious way of life really endure such a high degree of inconclusiveness? Or put differently, can pluralism comport with absolutes? The conventional answer, in our time, is that it cannot, and so it must be something else. It must be perspectivism, or pragmatism, or relativism. The contemporary discussion of these questions by Jewish commentators has been rather slavishly dominated by the anti-rationalist clichés of contemporary philosophy. My own view is that any attempt to relieve the argumentative tradition of its rationality; or to seek a release from its dissonance, by denying either its commitment to truth or its commitment to many-mindedness; or to reduce rational argument to the emotional expression of an individual or a group—all this represents both a misunderstanding of the achievement of the Jewish style of controversy and an impoverishment of it. Reason is often depicted as repressive and orthodox, but it is in fact open-ended and infinitely patient, which is why thinkers in our times are still arguing with thinkers in ancient times and building upon their work. The enterprise of argumentation is ancient but not antiquated.

Truth may be one, as Weil said—but even so, what is it? We live in the arduous interim between the belief in truth and the discovery of truth. It is never too late for a rational objection or a logical advance. The contemporary anxiety about reason is misplaced: Emotion is private and opaque, but reason is public and lucid. This is proven on every serious Jewish bookshelf. Judaism evolved and progressed and flourished as an alliance of the heart and the head. The heart alone would not have sufficed, certainly not for a tradition whose essential act is the act of interpretation. 

Comments

  1. colinkaroo

    Leon, I am a great admirer of your writings, but this piece must be considered plain bullsh.t. You write this article as all of your articles precisely in order to seek agreement with your views. You cannot write an article the point of which would be to promote disagreement with the argument you raise. Thereby you create a paradox. By disagreeing with your proposition I simultaneously both agree with it and disagree with it. This violates Aristotle's postulate that nothing can be both A and not-A at the same time

  2. Dimnah

    Interesting article. I wholeheartedly agree with its conclusion that there can be such a thing as reasonable disagreement and that the Rabbinic tradition is an excellent example of such a model.

    I am also struck by how well the same argument could be made for the Islamic tradition. Muslim scholars agreed with the rabbi's that was one truth but that this one thruth belonged to God and was unattainable for humanity. Thus Islamic scholars adhered to a similar 'agree to disagree' model, where dissenting and/or minority opinions were safeguarded and often re-used in later times. (Needless to say this is a tradition that todays Islamists would rather ignore for obvious reasons.)

    This detour does bring me to a problem with the model described. Because for all their dissenting opinions, the rabbi's and the ulama did agree on the fundamentals. They shared a belief in one God, a common plight, and a methodology. Their argumentative practice thus presupposed an underlying holistic model. As stated it was in fact a quarrelsome unity in diversity. But isn't the problem of today's society exactly that we don't share such clear common denominators? And might this not precisely be why contemporary philosophy so often falls into relativism, pragmatism, or even nihilism?

  3. Toronto

    Another classic version of this is the slow drift of Socratic representation away from the (perhaps? probably?) original character of Socrates who has faith in the power of argument to work towards the truth, towards a Socrates who believes in absolutes. This was at least Gregory Vlastos' interpretation -- that Plato was puzzled about how Socrates seems to assume that his method of sitting in the agora arguing with people towards truth could work; and so eventually Plato had to come up with a theory, first, that we were remembering pre-life ideas (the Meno) and then that there were these "Ideas" (later dialogues). And Socrates stops arguing and starts pontificating.

  4. IW

    I think you might enjoy reading Walter Bagehot's essay on the "metaphysical basis of toleration," in which he makes a very similar point, arguing, for example, that "no man is on all points so wise as the mass of men are after a good discussion, and that if the ideas of the very wisest were by miracle to be fixed on the race, the certain result would be to stereotype monstrous error."

  5. aneeman

    In response to colinkaroo's comment, "By disagreeing with your proposition I simultaneously both agree with it and disagree with it. This violates Aristotle's postulate that nothing can be both A and not-A at the same time"

    Paradoxes of this nature are frequent in Jewish intellectual tradition, and, as Leon points out, essential to well functioning democratic societies and pluralistic intellectual traditions, where we recognize that conflicting values require a balancing act that rarely, if ever, yields a single final determination of what is or is not ethical or appropriate. The Jewish tradition has always acknowledged that tension and conflict are important and inevitable elements of the search for truth and ethics, and that the analytic process through which this tension and conflict is managed is just as important as the results it yields. In many ways, it is more important, because different results will come to different commentators, but the common analytical framework that both sides use sets precedents and informs future debates in the Jewish community and tradition.

    As Leon articulates, this is not moral relativism or utilitarianism. Our tradition acknowledges absolute concepts like good, evil, right, wrong, equality, truth, justice and other such heavenly concepts. We believe in those things. We just recognize that the process of deriving their meaning and weighing different facets of them against each other is an inherently debate-ridden process, not likely to yield the same or conclusive results for all participants.

  6. nw47

    Mr Wieseltier, It would be much easier to understand your article without the dedication. Is it in appreciation? In admonition? Other? Are you addressing a local problem in a national forum? Please say more. You can hardly leave it as it is.

  7. Carabal

    Mr. Wieseltier, You state, "It may be found in ancient and early modern India, as Amartya Sen showed in his great essay “The Argumentative Indian,”"

    and immediately, you jump to, "but its most sophisticated and most robust home is in Judaism, from its beginnings in ancient rabbinical literature all the way to the present day. The Jewish tradition—the tradition of the argumentative Jew—is a long and great challenge to the consensualist mentality.""

    That's quite a self-absorbed leap that is disrespectful to Indian philosophical traditions as well as our own rich Jewish scholarship. I'll take license from the thesis of your essay and uninhibitedly say, "A lot of baloney, sir!" I'm familiar with both the Talmudic and the Dharmic sides and I'd be intellectually dishonest to if I did not say that the Indians have a very rich and intense tradition of argumentation. A lot of Vedic and Upanishadic studies, discourses, transmission (from Guru to Sishya, from School to School, tradition to tradition...) happened orally since their recording material was not of a strong, durable property that enabled repeated handling by many pupils (Palm leaves as against our papyrus). In fact, many new traditions formed by argumentation. For example, Nagarjuna (called the "Second Buddha") was born a poor Brahmin in a hamlet in far, far away southern India. As a young man, he moved from place to place, guru to guru, tradition to tradition arguing with great thinkers along the way until he reached way up north (of India) where, with the crystallized wisdom, The Fundamentals of the Middle Way. [We distinguish him as a Buddhist but there were no distinctions between various dharmic traditions in those days]. Anyway, Nagarjuna's Middle Way was not only a philosophy but also a proposal for a dialectic methodology that is rooted in the one vital tradition: purvapaksha which literally means argumentation. Interested readers can check it out readily on the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://www.iep.utm.edu/category/traditions/indian/) although your library might have richer choices. Anyway, I think, for a literary critic, you're really getting ahead of yourself, Mr. Wieseltier. Have you read the Argumentative Indian, by the way? I doubt it.....

  8. gwhepner

    THE NEW REPUBLIC’S LITERARY DECEDITOR

    Distinguished intellectual Leon Wieseltier is described as The New Republic’s literary editor
    in an article on Jewish argument, called mahloqet.
    to which he gives deserved praise while choosing not to mock it,
    but since the magazine is dead as Latin, he’s become its literary deceditor.

    Leon Wieseltier is described, in an article he wrote for the Winter 2015 Jewish Review of Books called “The Argumentative Jew,” as the literary editor of The New Republic. That is sadly no longer true, since magazine died in early December 2014. The demise has been well described by Dana Milbank in The Washington Post (“The New Republic is dead, thanks to its owner, Chris Hughes,” 12/8/14). I don’t know whether Mr. Wieseltier was ripped off by its new owner, Chris Hughes, but let this verse serve as a Latinizing R. I. P. for TNR’s quondam literary editor.

    [email protected]

  9. asmith

    Mr. Hepner,

    At the time this issue went to press, The New Republic had not yet imploded, and Mr. Wieseltier was still the literary editor. The digital issue has been updated to note that this is his former position. Mr. Wieseltier continues as a member of the Jewish Review of Books' editorial board and contributor.

    Amy Newman Smith
    Associate Editor

Suggested Reading

Pogrom: A Poem

Amichai Chasson

Will the hunters come again to our abode tonight, seeking our souls with gun threats? Will they come quiet and furtive, until the crack of a shot cuts through the crickets? Perhaps they will arrive with a shofar blast like the lords of the land subduing the world, bringing their sons to teach them the wiles of war, carrying our…